(This was the basis for a talk I gave at the Toronto Student Set Theory and Topology seminar on January 15, 2013. The assumed knowledge is an undergraduate course in general topology. This is only a draft, and will be updated soon.)
Introduction
There are many questions in mathematics and sciences in general whose main object of study is the topological group. These objects are very versatile and can represent many of the structures we encounter. One question that I’ve been working on examines the (extreme) dynamical properties of topologies on the integers. On the recommendation of Vladimir Pestov (one of my advisors) I have been learning about T-sequences, which provide a rich method for producing topological groups with extreme behaviour. Here I will present two techniques involving T-sequences that help to answer two different questions about topological groups; one is about dynamics and the other is about combinatorial properties of . These results all come from “Topologies on the Integers” by Protasov and Zelenyuk.
The Words You Should Know
Definition. A sequence is a T-sequence (in
) if there is a topology
on
such that
is a
group topology in which
converges to 0. (i.e. Every open neighbourhood of
contains a tail of
).
Definition. For a T-sequence we let
be the strongest
topological group where
converges to
.
In general we will think of a T-sequence as being a (relatively) quickly growing sequence. How fast? Well we will be thinking about geometric series. A T-sequence needs to be at least a little sparse as the next sequence illustrates.
(Non-)example 1. Let be an ennumeration of
. It cannot be a T-sequence. This is because any open set must be co-finite. So a topology in which this converges would not be
.
Example 2. In contrast, trival T-sequences are sequences that end in a tail of zeros. These sequences converge in with the discrete topology.
(Non-)example 3. An arithmetic progression cannot be a T-sequence. We will see this later.
Example 4. The geometric progression is a T-sequence. We will also see this later
The Canonical Topology
Suppose that is a sequence in
and let
be an non-decreasing function. When
is a T-sequence, a basis for its topology in which
converges to 0 is given by
, (with
to be defined), but the notation will not require
to be a T-sequence.
Define , to be the tail of the sequence (after
).
For define
, the symmetrization of
, where
.
Finally, .
Lemma 1. Fix a (not necessarily T-)sequence
:
-
,
-
,
-
,
-
such that
,
-
such that
.
Proof. The first three are obvious from staring. For 4, take to be the pointwise maximum of
, (as Stevo said: “It is so simple!”.). For 5, let
and
. [QED]
This tells us that forms a neighbourhood base of
for some group topology on
. (All we are missing is
.)
Lemma 2. If
is a topological group and
converges to 0 in
, then for every neighbourhood
of 0, there is an
such that
.
proof. Since converges to 0 in
, then there is a tail
. Let
. Since
is a topological group, we can inductively create
such that
, and a tail
. Let
. We see that
, by construction. [QED]
Theorem 3. A sequence
in
is a T-sequence iff
. Thus,
is a neighbourhood base of
for any topological group
where
converges to
.
proof. If converges to 0 in some
topological group
, then Lemma 2 and
-ness will tell you
. For the converse, the intersection being empty tells us that the group topology for which
forms a neighbourhood base of
is in fact a
group topology. [QED]
Recognizing T-sequences
The first thing we observe is a characterization of T-sequences, by restating Theorem 3.
Corollary 4. A sequence
is a T-sequence iff
.
This tells us why arithmetic sequences (example 3) do not form T-sequences.
Somehow we would like to transfer this characterization to something “more finite”.
Definition. Let be any sequence in
. For
, we define
That is, is the set of
-sums taken from
.
Theorem 5. A sequence
is a T-sequence iff
.
That is, for each non-zero integer (), if the enemy fixes an amount (
) of sums we can take, there is a tail (
) with which we will not be able to make that non-zero integer as a
-sum taken from
.
Proof. The picture is very helpful here, and there is a neat method involved. The next proof will show it off.
Theorem 6 (Exercise 2.1.2). Let and
be T-sequences with corresponding topologies
and
. The following are equivalent:
;
we have
Before we go on the the proof, what is this saying? The big picture is that it is giving us a way to compare two topologies if we know something about how the sequences relate. We would like to say that iff
almost contains
, this just isn’t true. (If we know that one sequence almost contains the other, then we do get that the topologies are comparable, but we don’t get the other direction.)
The second alternative of the theorem should be interpreted as a way of saying that even though isn’t almost a subset of
, you can still (robustly) find tails of
as small finite combinations of elements of
.
proof. [To be included in a later edit.]
There are a lot of T-sequences
We now turn to the question of how many T-sequences there are in . First, an obvious observation.
Lemma 6. Every subsequence of a T-sequence is again a T-sequence.
Corollary 7. There are
-many T-sequences in
.
So there are lots of T-sequences, in fact there are as many as there could be, but many of these can generate the same topologies. Defining what it means to be “different”, we see that there are -many different T-sequences.
Definition. Two (non-trivial) T-sequences are strongly incomparable if there are neighbourhoods of the identity
and
such that
.
We are going to show the following three Theorems, using two combinatorial facts. One fact will say that every T-sequence contains two strongly incomparable T-sequences, and the second will say that every T-sequence can be refined to an alternative sequence, i.e., every (infinite-coinfinite) subsequence is strongly incomparable with its complement.
Theorem 8. There is a family of pairwise strongly incomparable T-sequences.
Theorem 9. There is a family of T-sequences such that if
then
is refined by
.
Theorem 10. There is a family of T-sequences such that if
then
is refined by
.
Combinatorial Fact 11. Every T-sequence contains two strongly incomparable T-sequences.
Combinatorial Fact 12. Every T-sequence contains an alternative subsequence
. That is, if
, disjoint, both infinite, then
and
are strongly incomparable.
Question (Protasov and Zelenyuk, 1999): Is there always a decreasing (or equivalently, increasing) chain, of topologies given by T-sequences, of order type ?
Question: Does there exist a topological group G so that for every non-trivial T-sequence (one that does not have a tail consisting solely of 0s) there is a nontrivial
(g not the identity) so that
converges to the identity of G?
LikeLike
Do you mean: “For each non-trivial T-sequence we can find a g, and a sequence of integers
so that
converges to the identity?”
My initial guess is yes, with G being the infinite product of
, with n increasing. This seems like cheating though.
LikeLike