When people ask me what I do I often give the ‘sexy answer’ that I study different sizes of infinity. This usually dazzles the listener and lets me talk about why I think math is beautiful as opposed to why it is useful “for getting chicks and dollar bills”.
Of course when a mathematician asks me what I do I need to give a more precise answer. (Also, I feel like, to many mathematicians, the study of cardinality seems like a parlor trick. “Been there, done that.”) So I’m going to give two (easy) facts that illustrate the types of results that go past the study of cardinality and peek into the world of infinite combinatorics.
The first observation is that people in set theory and set theoretic topology are obsessed with the real numbers (affectionately, “the reals”). Often discussions start with “This fact is true of the reals, but what about in other spaces?”. (For example, the reals have a countable dense subset – the rationals – and this is important enough that we gave it a name – separable.) Often in set theoretic topology we work under the heuristic that “everything is true in the reals”, and we look for which particular topological properties give us those facts.
So, it shouldn’t be surprising that we look for copies of the reals wherever we can.
Fact 1. There is a copy of the reals inside of the partial order 
Here
means
for some
. This just means that
is almost contained in
. Another way to think of this partial order is that two sets are equivalent when they differ in only finitely many places. In plainspeak, besides finitely many exceptions, every element of
is also in
. (Also,
is the family of all subsets of the natural numbers.)
proof of Fact 1. We need to construct a family of sets
such that when
we get
. Also, we should make sure that we didn’t construct something trivial. We should make sure that when
that
and
disagree on an infinite set.
Fix a bijection
. Let
.
Sure enough, this has the above property that
implies
. The non triviality condition is given because whenever
there are infinitely many rationals between
and
. [QED]
There are other things to say about this partial order (along the lines of “It contains a copy of every countable partial order”), but I will leave those for another time.
The next thing is a standard fact that is often given as a challenge exercise for undergraduates.
Fact 2. There is a family
such that if
then
is finite.
We will also have that each
is infinite. (Can you see what happens if we don’t insist on this?)
As a warm up, try finding an infinite (not necessarily uncountable) family with that property. (In this case you can do much better; you can make is so that the intersection of any two sets is empty.)
proof of Fact 2. Fix a bijection
. For each
, fix a sequence
of rationals that converges to
.
Note that if
then
is finite, because the two sequences are converging to two different reals.
So
is the desired family. [QED]
There you go! Two facts that show how infinite combinatorics goes beyond just showing that
.